Home
Rothbard Pledge
Strategic Questions
Ten Points
Participate
History
Essays:
Why Be Libertarian?
(Rothbard)
Strategies for a Libertarian Victory
(Rothbard)
The Importance of the Caucus
(Rothbard)
LP Resolutions:
On Strategy
On Coalitions
Audio:
Plumb-Line Libertarianism
(
Walter
Block
)
|
Murray
Rothbard's
Strategies For A Libertarian Victory
was condensed
from a longer paper dated April, 1977 and entitled "Toward A
Strategy For Libertarian Social Change". This 178 page, double
spaced, typewritten manuscript was written for an informal private
symposium, out of which grew the Cato Institute and several activist
organizations, as well as an energized Libertarian Party, which had
been founded a few years earlier. The original paper, which has never
been published, contains Rothbard's analysis of several libertarian
and non-libertarian political movements in addition to the conceptual
framework outlined here.
This condensed
version appeared first in
Libertarian Review,
August, 1978,
which was published by the Cato Institute. Rothbard also condensed
some of these ideas into Part V of
The Ethics of Liberty,
a section entitled "Toward A Theory of Strategy for Liberty."
After a simmering
dispute over strategy, starting with the 1980 Clark for President
campaign, and ending with a bruising battle in 1983 over the party's
presidential candidate, the Cato contingent left the LP, never to
return. A few years later Rothbard also left the LP as a result
of his own dissatisfaction with its strategic direction. For details,
see
An Enemy of the State,
by Justin Raimondo (Prometheus
Books, 2000), the illuminating and inspiring story of Rothbard and
his life's work. Also see
Murray N. Rothbard: A Legacy of Liberty
for an outline of Rothbard's prodigious
lifetime output.
My own small
role in the LP at the time included membership in the Central Committee
of the Libertarian Party Radical Caucus, founded in February, 1979
by Raimondo and Eric Garris, and dedicated, at least in part, to
applying the Rothbardian insights to party strategy. Rothbard himself
was a member of the Central Committee until the LPRC was torn apart
at the 1983 presidential nominating convention (see Raimondo's book
for the full story). Earlier, after I became editor of the LPRC's
publications, it was decided to reprint this essay; here you see
a faithful reproduction of the pamphlet that was produced. The epilogue
was almost certainly written by Raimondo.
In the fall
of 2003 it came to my attention that a member of the platform committee
of the Libertarian Party has not read this essay, this in a year
when the committee is attempting a major rewrite of the platform
in order to accommodate both "idealists" and "pragmatists".
Taking my cue from Rothbard's beloved Mises Institute, which has
made so much valuable material readily available, I dug out the
essay and fired up my scanner. Murray never warmed to the idea of
using a computer himself, but I'm sure he would have approved of
these important ideas being spread as far and as widely as possible
via the network of computers that is the Internet. So if you think
others should see this, please pass it along.
This important
essay has been inaccessible for too long. I believe that every libertarian,
capital "L" or not, who hopes for an actual libertarian
victory, should use these concepts as the basis for his or her own
analysis of strategy. Does this mean that all will then agree on
what strategy to follow? Certainly not, but the discussion of strategy
will be clarified and enhanced to the extent that these Rothbardian
insights are not ignored.
Scott Olmsted
Encinitas, California
February 21, 2004
Strategies
For A Libertarian Victory (pdf file - 229 KB)
Mail
this file to a libertarian!
Strategies
For A Libertarian Victory
by
Murray N. Rothbard
Copyright
2012 Mises.org
L
ibertarians
have given considerable
thought
to refining
their basic principles and their vision of a libertarian society.
But they have given virtually no thought to a vitally important
question, that of strategy: Now that we know the nature of our social
goal, how in the world do we get there?
To the extent that libertarians have thought at all about strategy
it has simply been to adopt what I have called "educationism:"
namely, that actions rest upon ideas, and therefore that libertarians
must try to convert people to their ideas by issuing books, pamphlets,
articles, lectures, etc. Now, it is certainly true that actions
depend upon ideas, and that education in libertarian ideas is an
important and necessary part in converting people to liberty and
in effecting social change. But such an insight is only the
beginning
of
arriving at a libertarian strategy; there is a great deal
more that needs to be said.
In the first place, ideas do not spread and advance by themselves
in a social vacuum; they must be adopted and spread by
people,
people
who must be convinced of and committed to the progress
of liberty. But this means that liberty can advance only by means
of a developing libertarian
movement.We
must therefore be
concerned not only with the ideology but also with developing the
people to carry the principles forward.
Webster'sdefines
"movement" in a way clearly relevant to our concerns:
"A connected and long continued series of acts and events tending
toward some more or less definite end; an agitation in favor of
some principle, policy etc., as the Tractarian
movement;the
prohibition
movement."
Some libertarians have criticized the very concept of "movement"
as "collectivist," as somehow violating the principles
of individualism. But it should be clear that there is nothing in
the least collectivist in individuals voluntarily joining together
for the advancement of common goals. A libertarian movement is no
more "collectivist" than a corporation, a bridge club,
or any other organization; it is curious that some libertarians,
while conceding the merits of all other such "collective"
organizations, balk only at one that would advance the cause of
liberty itself. Neither does joining amovement mean thatthe joiner must in some way submerge his individual sovereignty
to the movement or the organization, any more than the bridge club
member must submerge his individuality in order to advance the playing
of bridge. The individual libertarian, who places the triumph of
liberty high on his value scale, decides to join a movement which
is requisite to the achievement of his goal, just as does the member
of a bridge club or the investor in a steel manufacturing corporation.
If the advancement of liberty requires a movement as well as a body
of ideas, it is our contention that the overriding goal of a libertarian
movement must be the
victory of libertyin
the real world,
the bringing of the ideal into actuality. This may seem a truism,
but unfortunately many libertarians have failed to see the importance
of victory as the ultimate and overriding goal.
But why should libertarians
notadopt
what might seem to
be a self-evident goal? One reason for not making such a commitment
is that a person may prefer the libertarian ideal as an intellectual
game, something to be merely contemplated without relevance to the
real world; another reason for weakening a person's desire to pursue
the goal of victory may be a profound pessimism that he may feel
about any future prospects for victory. In any case, holding the
victory of liberty as one's primary goal is only likely in those
persons whose libertarianism is motivated and molded by
a passion
for justice:
by
a realization that statism is unjust, and by
a desire to eliminate such glaring injustice as swiftly as possible.
Hence, the utilitarian, who is concerned not for justice and moral
principle but only for increased productivity or efficiency, may
believe in liberty as an ideal, but is not likely to place passionate
commitment into achieving it. The utilitarian, by his nature, is
far more likely to remain content with partial success than to press
on to complete victory. Indeed, such a weakening of the will toward
victory was partly responsible for the decline of classical liberalism
in the nineteenth century.
It
necessarily
follows, from our primary goal of victory,
that we want victory as
quickly
as possible. If victory is
indeed our given end, an end given to us by the requirements of
justice, then we must strive to achieve that end as rapidly as we
can.
But this means that libertarians must not adopt gradualism as part
of their goal; they must wish to achieve liberty as early and as
rapidly as possible. Otherwise, they would be ratifying the continuation
of injustice. They must be "abolitionists."
The objection is often raised that abolitionism is "unrealistic",
that liberty (or any other radical social goal) can be achieved
only gradually. Whether or not this is true (and the existence of
radical upheavals demonstrates that such is not always the case),
this common charge gravely confuses the realm of principle with
the realm of strategy. As I have written elsewhere
by
making such a charge they are hopelessly confusing the desired
goal with a strategic estimate of the probable outcome. In framing
principle, it is of the utmost importance not to mix in strategic
estimates with the forging of desired goals. First, one must formulate
one's goals, which . . . would be the instant abolition of slavery
or whatever other statist oppression we are considering. And we
must first frame these goals without considering the probability
of attaining them. The libertarian goals are "realistic"
in the sense that they could be achieved if enough people agreed
on their desirability . . . The "realism" of the goal
can only be challenged by a critique of the goal
itself,
not in the problem of how to attain it. Then, after we have decided
on the goal, we face the entirely separate strategic question
of how to attain that goal as rapidly as possible, how to build
a movement to attain it, etc. Thus, William Lloyd Garrison was
not being "unrealistic" when, in the 1830s, he raised
the glorious standard of immediate emancipation of the slaves.
His goal was the proper one, and his strategic realism came in
the fact that he did not expect his goal to be quickly reached.
Or, as Garrison himself distinguished: "Urge immediate abolition
as earnestly as we may, it will, alas! be gradual abolition in
the end. We have never said that slavery would be overthrown by
a single blow; that it ought to be, we shall always contend. (
Egalitarianism
as a Revolt Against Nature
, p. 150)
From
a strictly strategic point of view, it is also true that if the
adherents of the "pure" goal do not state that goal and
hold it aloft,
no one
will do so, and the goal therefore
will never be attained. Furthermore, since most people and most
politicians will hold to the "middle" of whatever "road"
may be offered them, the "extremist," by constantly raising
the ante, and by holding the pure or "extreme" goal aloft,
will move the extremes further over, and will therefore pull the
"middle" further over in his extreme direction. Hence,
raising the ante by pulling the middle further in his direction
will, in the ordinary pulling and hauling of the political process,
accomplish more for that goal, even in the day-by-day short run,
than any opportunistic surrender of the ultimate principle.
In her brilliant study of the strategy and tactics of the Garrison
wing of the abolitionist movement, Aileen Kraditor writes:
It
follows, from the abolitionist's conception of his role in society,
that the goal for which he agitated was not likely to be immediately
realizable. Its realization must follow conversion of an enormous
number of people, and the struggle must take place in the face
of the hostility that inevitably met the agitator for an unpopular
cause . . . The abolitionists knew as well as their later scholarly
critics that immediate and unconditional emancipation could not
occur for a long time. But unlike those critics they were sure
itwould
never come unless it were agitated for during
the long period in which it was impracticable . . . .
To have dropped the demand for
immediate
emancipation because
it was unrealizable at the time would have been to alter the nature
of the change for which the abolitionists were agitating. That
is, even those who would have gladly accepted gradual and conditional
emancipation had to agitate for immediate and unconditional abolition
of slavery because that demand was required by their goal of demonstrating
to white Americans that Negroes were their brothers. Once the
nation had been converted on that point, conditions and plans
might have been made. . . .
Their refusal to water down their "visionary" slogan
was, in their eyes, eminently practical, much more so than the
course of the antislavery senators and congressmen who often wrote
letters to abolitionist leaders justifying their adaptation of
anti-slavery demands to what was attainable. The abolitionist,
while criticizing such compromises, would insist that his own
intransigence made favorable compromises possible. He might have
stated his position thus: If politics is the art of the possible,
agitation is the art of the desirable. The practice of each must
be judged by criteria appropriate to its goal. Agitation by the
reformer or radical helps define one possible policy as more desirable
than another, and if skillful and uncompromising, the agitation
may help make the desirable possible. To criticize the agitator
for not trimming his demands to the immediately realizable--that
is, for not acting as a politician, is to miss the point. The
demand for a change that is not politically possible does not
stamp the agitator as unrealistic. For one thing, it can be useful
to the political bargainer; the more extreme demand of the agitator
makes the politician's demand seem acceptable and perhaps desirable
in the sense that the adversary may prefer to give up half a loaf
rather than the whole. Also, the agitator helps define the value,
the principle, for which the politician bargains. The ethical
values placed on various possible political courses are put there
partly by agitators working on the public opinion that creates
political possibilities. (Means and Ends in American Abolitionism,
1969; pp. 26-28)
*
* *
If
the primary and overriding goal
of the libertarian movement
must be the victory of liberty as rapidly as possible, then the
primary task of that movement must be to employ the most efficacious
means
to arrive at that goal.
To be efficacious, to achieve the goal of liberty as quickly as
possible, it should be clear that the means
must not contradict
the ends. For if they do, the ends are being obstructed instead
of pursued as efficiently as possible. For the libertarian, this
means two things: (1) that he must never deny or fail to uphold
the ultimate goal of libertarian victory; and (2) that he must never
use or advocate the use of unlibertarian means--of aggression against
the persons or just property of others. Thus, the libertarian must
never, for the sake of alleged expediency, deny or conceal his ultimate
objective of complete liberty; and he must never aggress against
others in the search for a world of nonaggression. For example,
the Bolsheviks, before the revolution, financed themselves partially
by armed robbery in the name of "expropriating" capitalists;
clearly, any use of aggression against private property in order
to finance the libertarian movement, in addition to being immoral
by libertarian principles, would cut against those principles themselves
and their ultimate attainment.
At this point,
any
radical movement for social change, including
the libertarian movement, has to face an important, realistic problem:
in the real world, the goal--for the libertarian, the disappearance
of the state and its aggressive coercion--unfortunately
cannot
be achieved overnight.
Libertarians
must not adopt gradualism as part of their goal; they must wish
to achieve liberty as early and as rapidly as possible. Otherwise,
they would be ratifying the continuation of injustice.
Since
that is the case, what should be the position of the libertarian
toward "transition demands," i.e., toward demands that
would move
toward
liberty without yet reaching the ultimate
goal? Wouldn't such demands undercut the ultimate goal of total
liberty itself?
In our view the proper solution to this problem is a "centrist"
or "movement-building" solution: namely, that it is legitimate
and proper to advocate transition demands as way-stations along
the road to victory,
provided that
the ultimate goal of victory
is always kept in mind and held aloft. In this way the ultimate
goal is clear and not lost sight of and the pressure is kept on
so that transitional or partial victories will feed on themselves
rather than appease or weaken the ultimate drive of the movement.
Thus, suppose that the libertarian movement adopts, as a transitional
demand, an across-the-board fifty percent cut in taxation. This
must be done in such a way as
not
to imply that a fifty-one
percent cut would somehow be immoral or improper. In that way the
fifty percent cut would simply be an
initial
demand rather
than an ultimate goal in itself, which would only undercut the libertarian
goal of total abolition of taxation.
Similarly, if libertarians should ever call for reducing or abolishing
taxes in some particular
area,
that call must
never
be accompanied by advocating the increase of taxation in some other
area. Thus, we might well conclude that the most tyrannical and
destructive tax in the modern world is the
incometax,
and
therefore that first priority should be given to abolishing that
form of tax. But the call for drastic reduction or abolition of
the income tax must never be coupled with advocating a
higher
tax
in some other area (e.g., a sales tax), for that indeed
would be employing a means contradictory to the ultimate goal of
tax abolition. Libertarians must, in short, hack away at the state
wherever and whenever they can, rolling back or eliminating state
activity in whatever area possible.
As an example, during every recession, Keynesian liberals generally
advocate an income tax cut to stimulate consumer demand. Conservatives,
on the other hand, generally oppose such a tax cut as leading to
higher government deficits. The libertarian, in contrast, should
always and everywhere support a tax cut as a reduction in state
robbery.
Then,when
the budget is discussed, the libertarian
should
alsosupport
a reduction in government expenditures
to eliminate a deficit. The point is that the state must be opposed
and whittled down in every respect and at every point: in cutting
taxes or in cutting government expenditures. To advocate raising
taxes or to oppose cutting them in order to balance the budget is
to oppose and undercut the libertarian goal.
But while the ultimate goal of total liberty must always be upheld
and the state must be whittled down at every point, it is still
proper, legitimate, and necessary for a libertarian movement
to
adopt priorities
,
to agitate against the state most particularly
in those areas which are most important at any given time. Thus,
while the libertarian opposes both income and sales taxes, it is
both morally proper and strategically important to select, say,
the income tax as the more destructive of the two and to agitate
more against that particular tax. In short, the libertarian movement,
like everyone else, faces a scarcity of its own time, energy and
funds, and it must allocate these scarce resources to their most
important uses at any given time. Which particular issues should
receive priority depends on the specific conditions of time and
place.
Within any radical ideological movement for social change there
are bound to develop two broad and important "deviations"
from the correct, centrist, movement-building position we have been
discussing. At one pole is the deviation of "left-sectarianism"
and at the other the deviation of "right-opportunism."
Each, in its own way abandons the hope of victory for the radical
goal. The left sectarian, in brief, considers
any
transition
demands, any use of strategic intelligence to determine priorities
for agitation, any appeal to one's audience without sacrificing
ultimate principles, in themselves a "sellout" or betrayal
of radical principles. In the above example, a left sectarian, for
example, would consider the transition call for repeal of the income
tax per se a betrayal of the principle of the abolition of taxation,
even though that transition demand were clearly coupled with the
ultimate goal of a tax-free society. To take a deliberately ludicrous
example, the left sectarian might consider
not raising
the
problem of denationalizing lighthouses in our current society a
betrayal of the principle of privatizing lighthouses.
In the libertarian movement, sectarians will simply reiterate such
formulas as the nonaggression axiom, or A is A, or the need for
self-esteem, without grappling with detailed issues. The centrist
position, in contrast, is to begin agitation around currently important
issues, examine them, show the public that the cause of these problems
is statism and that the solution is liberty, and
thentry
to widen the consciousness of one's listeners to show that all current
and even remote problems have the same political cause.
One form that left-sectarianism sometimes takes is that of advocating
immediate armed revolution against the existing state, without sufficient
support to be able to succeed. In the modern libertarian movement,
this deviation was pervasive during its early stage, at the time
of the New Left "revolution" in the late 1960s and 1970.
The collapse of the latter "revolution" as soon as the
state began its armed counteraction at Kent State is testimony to
one of the most important lessons of history: that
no armed revolution
has
ever succeeded in a country with free elections. All the
successful revolutions, from the American and the
To
the "left sectarian,"
any
transition demands, any
use of strategic intelligence to determine priorities for agitation,
is a "sellout," or betrayal of radical principles.
French
in the eighteenth century, to the Russian, Chinese, and Cuban in
the twentieth, occurred in lands where free elections were either
nonexistent or severely restricted. Until or unless the United States
changes from free elections to dictatorship, the question of armed
revolution is, at the very least, totally irrelevant to the American
scene.
In contrast to left-sectarianism, which spurns immediate gains toward
the ultimate goal, right-wing opportunists openly believe in hiding
or working against their ultimate goal in order to achieve short
run gains.
Right-wing opportunism is self-defeating for ultimate goals in several
ways. The major reason for putting forth transition demands is as
a
way-station
to ultimate victory; but, by studiously avoiding
the raising of ultimate goals or principles, the opportunist, at
best, short-circuits the ultimate goal, and betrays it by failing
to raise the consciousness of the public in the
explicit
direction of the final goal. The ultimate goal will not be reached
automatically by itself; it can only be reached if a large group
of adherents continues to hold high the banner of that ultimate,
radical objective. But, if
libertarians
refuse to examine
and put forward their ultimate goals,
who will?
The answer
is no one, and therefore that objective will never be attained.
Indeed, if libertarians fail to keep their ultimate objective in
view, they will themselves lose sight of the objective, and descend
into another gradualist,
nonlibertarian
reform movement,
and the main purpose of having a movement in the first place will
be lost. Secondly, opportunists often undercut the ultimate objective,
and libertarian principle as well, by openly advocating measures
that undercut the principle--such as a higher sales tax to replace
an income tax (as did the Mid-Hudson chapter of the Free Libertarian
Party in early 1976), or a gradualist Four-Year Plan to advertise
their moderation and alleged reasonableness.
Even in the short run, opportunism is self-destructive. Any new
ideological movement or party, in order to acquire support--as in
the case of new products or firms on the market--must
differentiate
its product
from
its established competitors. A Libertarian
Party which, for example, sounds almost indistinguishable from right-wing
Republicanism (as did the Tuccille campaign for New York governor
in 1974), will fail if only because the voter presented with no
clear alternative will quite rationally remain with right-wing Republicans.
In sum,
both
strategic deviations are fatal to the proper
goal of the victory of liberty as soon as it can be achieved; left-sectarianism
because it in effect abandons
victory,
and right-opportunism
because it in effect abandons
liberty.
Both sides of this
"equation" must be continually upheld.
One obvious propensity is that of a certain number of individuals,
in the libertarian and other radical movements, to shift rapidly
from one diametrically opposed deviation to the other, without
ever
passing through the correct, centrist position. Apart from psychological
instability among these individuals, there is a certain logic to
these seemingly bizarre leaps. Take, for example, someone who for
years confines his activities to stating pure principle, without
ever doing anything in the real world to transform reality. After
several years, discouragement at the lack of progress may set in,
after which, desperate for
some
gains in the real world,
the person leaps into right-opportunism and accomplishes little
there as well. On the other hand, someone mired in short run opportunism
for years, disgusted with the compromises and immorality of
that
form of politics, can readily express his disgust and his yearning
for pure principle by leaping straight into sectarianism. In neither
manifestation, however, is the individual willing to engage in a
protracted, lifelong commitment for victory in the real world
for
principle and as quickly as the goal can be achieved.
*
* *
I
have touched on the concept of "cadre." Let us
now
consider the concept in more detail; specifically, who make up the
cadre, how is it generated, and what are the proper relations between
cadre and various groups of non-cadre?
The cadre are simply the consistent libertarians. In the first place,
libertarianism is a
set of ideas,
and hence the original
cadre are bound to be largely intellectuals, people who are professional
or semiprofessional dealers in abstract ideas. Mises and Hayek have
pointed out how ideas filter out from original theoreticians to
scholars and followers, to intellectuals as dealers in general ideas,
and then to the interested public. Thus the body of intellectuals
is of prime importance in influencing the general movement and,
ultimately, the general public.
It is to be hoped that the cadre begins as a tiny few and then grows
in quantity and impact. But what should be the proper relationship
between cadre and noncadre? First, we might put forward the concept
of the "pyramid of ideology." For while "cadre"
and "noncadre" may be a first approximation to the real
world situation, the actual condition at any given time is akin
to a pyramid, with the cadre at the top of the ideological pyramid
as the consistent and uncompromising ideologists, and then with
others at lower rungs, with varying degrees of approximation to
a consistent and comprehensive libertarian vision. Since people
usually become cadre by making their way up the various steps or
stages of the pyramid--from totally nonlibertarian to completely
libertarian, some rapidly, some slowly, this implies that the stages
will assume a pyramid form, with a smaller number of people at each
higher stage.
The major task of the cadre, then, is to try to get as many people
as high up the pyramid as possible. From this task, there follows
the importance of ideological
coalitions,
of working with
allies on various ideological issues.
A coalition accomplishes several things. In the first place, it
maximizes the influence of the numerically small cadre on important
social issues, and does so by allying oneself with people who agree
on that particular issue,
albeit on few others.
On
which issues
the cadre chooses to form alliances and work
depends on a judgment of importance in relation to the real world
context at the given time and place. Thus, it would be an evident
waste of time and energy for libertarians today to find shipping
interests with whom to make a united front agitation in the cause
of denationalizing lighthouses. But coalition strategies for abolishing
OSHA or the income tax, or legalizing marijuana, or (in the late
1960s) pulling out of the Vietnam War or repealing the draft, might
have a high priority in the agitation of the libertarian movement.
While using coalitions with numerically larger allies on concrete
issues, the libertarian cadre is also pursuing another strategy--recruiting
more people. These recruits can come from the allies themselves,
or from the mass of the public who are being informed about the
specific issues. Normally, the proper tactic will be to
begin
with the concerns of the people being worked on, to show that you
are with them on this particular issue, and
then
to "widen
their libertarian consciousness" by showing them that to be
really
consistent on the issues they favor they must also
adopt the other libertarian positions. Thus, while working with
left-wing civil libertarians in support of commonly held positions,
it can be pointed out to them that libertarians are the only
consistent
civil liberties advocates, that personal freedom cannot exist without
private property rights, etc. Similarly, conservative advocates
of free enterprise can be shown that outlawing pornography or drugs
violates the very system of private property and free enterprise
that they
profess
to favor.
Of course, there are pitfalls in a coalition strategy that must
be guarded against. In the late 1960s, I issued a call for a libertarian
affiance with the New Left, on the twin vital issues of the day:
opposition to the draft and to the Vietnam War (with subsidiary
emphasis on opposition to the public school system). I still think
that this basic thrust was necessary--especially to generate a sharp
and radical break with the conservative movement. But the problem
was that many of our young, tiny cadre, upon cooperating with the
left,
became
leftists, losing their libertarian grip.
The libertarian movement at that time had two grave weaknesses that
left us wide open for such defection: (1) it was very small, and
therefore had no self-conscious cadre, no organs of opinion, no
mutually reinforcing cadre to talk to and deal with, and (2) partly
as a result of this tiny size, the libertarian movement of that
day had no
activity
with which to attract young and eager
libertarians. Many is the time when a new convert to the libertarian
system would ask: OK, now I'm a libertarian, what can I
do
about it? What
activity
can I perform? There was no answer.
If a person were a budding young scholar he could go to graduate
school and join the educational wing of the movement; but what if
he were not? As a result, the defections from cadre, not just to
the New Left but to dropping out altogether, were legion.
And this is one of the main reasons why the Libertarian Party has
been such a vital and important development in the last few years:
It has given to eager young (and older) libertarians a wide and
open-ended field for continuing an energetic
activity.In
short, because of the LP, we have become a genuine
movementrather
than just a small group of thinkers and talkers (as important as
the latter functions may be).
This is also why it is very important to have "open centers"
for libertarians--organizations for budding libertarians to visit
and study, institutions which demonstrate the existence of an organized
ideology and movement. For I am convinced that, for many reasons,
including the libertarian heritage that is partially imbibed by
most Americans, there are many people who are "instinctively"
and inchoately libertarian and don't know it, and who need only
a few open reiterations of the pure radical creed to join us.
Finding
the
movement becomes extremely important for isolated actual
or potential cadre. In the late 1940s and for years afterwards,
for example, FEE provided the enormous service of being the only
open center for
laissez-fairein
and Iexistence,
vividly remember the vital importance to me and other young libertarians
of discovering libertarian ideas and persons through FEE, and the
effect this stimulus and reinforcement had in radicalizing our own
positions.
*
* *
One
of the most important problems
for any minority radical movement
is the question of long run optimism or pessimism. Namely, while
the short run prospects for victory may be nonexistent, does the
movement believe that,
in the long run,
it will win? In my
"Left and Right: The Prospects for Liberty", I pointed
out that the conservative, here and in Europe, is always a long
run pessimist. The conservative believes that the inevitable march
of history is against him:
Hence,
the inevitable trend runs toward left-wing statism at home and
communism abroad. It is this long run despair that accounts for
the Conservative's rather bizarre short run optimism; for since
the long run is given up as hopeless, the Conservative feels that
his only hope of success rests in the current moment. In foreign
affairs, this point of view leads the Conservative to call for
desperate showdowns with communism, for he feels that the longer
he waits the worse things will inelectably become at home, it
leads him to total concentration on the very next election, where
he is always hoping for victory and never achieving it. The quintessence
of the Practical Man, and beset by long run despair, the Conservative
refuses to think or plan beyond the election of the day.
That conservatism rarely attracts youth is explainable by Randolph
Bourne's incisive comment that "our elders are always optimistic
in their views of the present, pessimistic in their views of the
future; youth is pessimistic toward the present and gloriously hopeful
for the future. And it is this hope which is the lever of progress
. . ."
Furthermore, conservatism, with its attachment to the feudalistic,
theocratic and. militaristic Old Order,
deserves
to be pessimistic.
Many libertarians also have tended to be long run pessimists, partly
in imitation of conservatism (with which some once were allied)
but partly because it is easy to be pessimistic in the twentieth
century if one focuses on the continuing advance of state power.
But to adopt this position is to fall prey to what the Marxists
call "impressionism"--i.e., responding only to the journalistic,
surface march of events without analyzing the underlying laws and
essences of the real world.
It should be obvious that long run optimism is important for the
success of any radical movement. In the libertarian movement, pessimism
has led either to despair, dropping out, confinement of the ideology
to an intellectual game, or to the opportunistic hankering for short
run gains that leads to betrayal of basic principle and which has
governed the conservative movement. On the other hand, long run
optimism leads both to a buoyant spirit and to the willingness to
engage in a protracted and determined struggle for ultimate goals.
All this is psychologically clear. But, if libertarianism is to
be grounded on a rational apprehension of reality, is long run optimism
the
correct
stance to take, or is it only a psychological
placebo?
It is my contention, which cannot be elaborated here, that libertarianism
will win,
and therefore that long run optimism is not only
psychologically exhilarating but also rationally correct. In "Left
and Right: The Prospects for Liberty" I elaborated the basic
reasons for this contention: that,
given
the commitment by
everyone, since the Industrial Revolution, to industrialism and
to mass consumption, the free market is the
only
economy
which enables the industrial system to survive and flourish and
continue to provide above-subsistence living standards for the growing
mass of population. In short, moral and economic truth is of course
on our side; but, in addition to this sometimes not very comforting
fact, freedom is
necessary
to the survival and prosperity
of the industrial world of the modern age.
But this, of course, can still be
very
long run, and might
be cold comfort to impatient spirits. In various writings since
1973-74, I have concluded that Mises's long run prediction of the
"exhaustion of the reserve fund"--that the unfortunate consequences
of government interventionism will one day become glaringly evident--has
now come true. We have seen in the past few years a host of crises:
inflationary recession, the breakdown of Keynesianism, crippling
tax rates, the failures of Vietnam; the revelations about the CIA,
FBI, and Watergate, the crises in crime and the public schools,
and much more. At least in the United States, the objective conditions
are now and will continue to exist for an accelerated leap forward
in libertarianism and for a rapid speeding up of the "timetable"
for victory.
I cannot believe that the visible great leap forward in the quantity
and quality of the libertarian movement since about 1973 is unrelated
to this new, continuing crisis of the American state. In short,
the growth in the "subjective conditions" for libertarian
victory (the libertarian cadre and movement) is partly a function
of the objective breakdown of statism.
As the Marxists point out, pessimism stems from impressionism and
the failure to think
dialectically.
In short, in libertarian
terms, while statism may be marching onward, this march inevitably
leads to a growing breakdown of statism which in turn leads to a
growing
reaction
in favor of libertarianism and against the
state.
The difference here between libertarians and Marxists stems from
their different theories. Thus, while the Marxists believe that
capitalism will founder on its "inevitable contradictions,"
giving rise to a proletarian movement for its eventual abolition,
libertarianism holds that
statism,
government interventionism,
will founder on
itsinevitable
"contradictions,"
and that this breakdown will give rise to a libertarian movement
among the public for its eventual abolition--and, further, if my
analysis of post-1973 is correct, that this breakdown of statism
has already begun.
Libertarian victory is thus inevitable
in the sense
that
objective breakdowns of statism are bound to intensify, and also
that such breakdowns will
tend
to give impetus to the growth
of libertarian ideas and activists, but, with our belief in individual
freedom of will, it is clear that the free and voluntary adoption
of libertarian ideas is not
determined
and therefore cannot
be inevitable in the strict sense. But victory
can
be achieved
if the libertarian movement continues to increase in quantity and
quality, and if libertarians continue to learn about current political
issues, bringing their analysis to bear on problems which the American
people face.
Many
libertarians tend to be long run pessimists, partly because it is
easy to be pessimistic in the twentieth century if one focuses on
the continuing advance of state power.
It is important for libertarians to realize that most people are,
in normal times, not
interested
in political affairs, and
therefore willing to continue passive or active support for the
status quo. It is only the development of "crisis situations"
(like skyrocketing property taxes in California), crises that result
from the breakdown of the existing system and with which the system
cannot cope, that the radical movement can accelerate its strength
and possibly achieve victory (as it did in the case of Proposition
13 in California). It is such periods of breakdown that stimulate
a massive willingness among the public to think deeply about the
social system and to consider radical alternatives. Such crisis
situations might be economic ones (such as depression or inflation
or skyrocketing taxes), a losing or a stalemated war, or political
repression of free speech and activity, or any combination of these.
These crisis situations, as well as the basic soil that prepare
them, constitute the necessary "objective conditions"
for a successful radical triumph. In addition to these requisite
objective conditions, there are also the "subjective conditions"--namely,
a movement of sufficient strength and influence to take advantage
of these objective conditions: specifically, to prepare in advance
by predicting the crisis, to point out how the crisis stems systematically
from the political system and is not simply an historical accident,
and to point to the radical alternative by which these crises and
others like them can be surmounted.
The ruling elite of America and elsewhere is beginning to lose its
self-confidence, to suffer a decay of its will. And this indeed
is another condition of victory. As Lawrence Stone has pointed out
in an analysis of the failure of the ruling class, "The elite
may lose its manipulative skill, or its military superiority, or
its self-confidence, or its cohesion; it may become estranged from
the non-elite, or overwhelmed by a financial crisis; it may be incompetent,
or weak or brutal."
(Causes of the American Revolution)
Thus, the objective conditions for the triumph of liberty have now,
in the past few years, arrived at last, at least in the United States.
Furthermore, the nature of this systemic crisis is such that government
is now perceived as the culprit; it cannot be relieved except through
a sharp turn toward liberty. Therefore, what is basically needed
now is the growth of the "subjective conditions," of libertarian
ideas and particularly of a dedicated libertarian movement to advance
those ideas in the public forum. Surely, it is no coincidence that
it is precisely in these years, from 1971 and particularly since
1973, that these subjective conditions have made their greatest
strides in this century. For the breakdown of statism has undoubtedly
spurred many more people into becoming partial or full libertarians,
and hence the objective conditions help to generate the subjective
ones. Furthermore, in the United States at least, the splendid heritage
of freedom and of libertarian ideas, going back beyond revolutionary
times, has never been fully lost. Present-day libertarians, therefore,
have solid historical ground on which to build.
The rapid growth in these last years of libertarian ideas and movements
has pervaded many fields of scholarship (especially among younger
scholars) and the areas of journalism, business, and politics. Because
of the continuing objective conditions, it seems clear that this
eruption of libertarianism in many new and unexpected places is
an inevitably growing response to the perceived conditions of objective
reality. Given free will, no one can predict with certainty that
the growing libertarian mood in America will solidify in a brief
period of time, and press forward without faltering to the success
of the entire libertarian program. But certainly, both theory and
analysis of current historical conditions lead to the conclusion
that the current prospects for liberty, even in the short run, are
excellent indeed.
Epilogue:
July, 1982
Since
the above essay was written in 1977-78,
events have provided
the libertarian movement with new problems and new opportunities.
The triumph of Reagan was partially the result of a popular backlash
against Big Government, mixed in, however, with very different thrusts
for moral theocracy and a war-hawk foreign policy. The Reagan Administration
has maintained the rhetoric of its free-market and other conservative
supporters, while betraying them down the line in action. It has
talked massive budget and tax cuts, while bringing us the highest
budget, the biggest deficit, and the largest tax increase in American
history. The abject failure of Reaganomics, including its consequence
in economic stagnation, chronic depression, and periodically accelerating
inflation, provides both a danger and an opportunity. An opportunity
if libertarians can convince the public of the Reagan betrayal and
that libertarians are the only ones who can sincerely lead an anti-Big
Government movement. A danger if the public becomes convinced that
free-market and libertarian ideas have already been tried and failed.
In any case, the major political task of libertarians is to separate
themselves, as sharply and as caustically as possible, from Reaganism,
Reaganomics, and the Reagan Administration. If not, libertarianism
will be discredited along with Reagan.
Murray
N. Rothbard is editor of the
Libertarian Forum,
member of
the Central Committee of the Libertarian Party Radical Caucus, and
the author of
For
A New Liberty, Man, Economy and State,
and
many other works on libertarian theory, economics, and history This
essay originally appeared in
Libertarian
Review,
August,
1978.
|